000 01363nam a2200205Ia 4500
999 _c9663
_d9663
005 20220222233537.0
008 200202s9999 xx 000 0 und d
082 _a320.5 LOC
100 _aLocke,John
245 0 _aSocial contract
260 _aLondon
260 _bOxford University
260 _c0
300 _a440p.
520 _aThas haunted the generations (it was current in the days of Plato, during the fourth century B.C., and it still flutters in the pages of Herbert Spencer's The Man versus the State at the end of the nineteenth century of our era), may be criticized on various grounds. The critic may urge that it was mechanical, and not organic, in its interpretation of political life; juristic, and not ethical, in its rationale of political obligation; a priori, and not historical, in its explanation of political society and political authority. The criticisms have their justice. The theory of the Social Contract could flourish only in an age, or 'climate', of thought in which the historical sense (the legacy left by the Romantic movement to the historians of the nineteenth century) was still imperfect and undeveloped. But if it was unhistorical, the theory was still historic-and historic in more than one sense.
650 _aPolitical Science
700 _aHume,David
700 _aRousseau,Jean-Jacques
942 _cB
_2ddc