000 | 01439nam a2200205Ia 4500 | ||
---|---|---|---|
999 |
_c214191 _d214191 |
||
005 | 20211122123206.0 | ||
008 | 200208s9999 xx 000 0 und d | ||
020 | _a9780521796286 | ||
082 | _a146.42 CAM | ||
100 | _a"Richardson,Alan (ed.)" | ||
245 | 0 | _aCambridge companion to logical empiricism/ edited by Alan Richardson and Thomas Uebel | |
260 | _aCambridge | ||
260 | _bCUP | ||
260 | _c2007 | ||
300 | _a430p. | ||
365 | _dUSD | ||
520 | _aIf there is a movement or school that epitomizes analytic philosophy in the middle of the twentieth century, it is logical empiricism. Logical empiricists created a scientifically and technically informed philosophy of science, established mathematical logic as a topic in and tool for philosophy, and initiated the project of formal semantics. Accounts of analytic philosophy written in the middle of the twentieth century gave logical empiricism a central place in the project. The second wave of interpretative accounts was constructed to show how philosophy should progress, or had progressed, beyond logical empiricism. The essays survey the formative stages of logical empiricism in central Europe and its acculturation in North America, discussing its main topics, and achievements and failures, in different areas of philosophy of science, and assessing its influence on philosophy, past, present, and future. | ||
650 | _aLogical positivism | ||
942 |
_cB _2ddc |